Qualia

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

The "redness" of red is a commonly used example of a quale.

In philosophy of mind, qualia (/ˈkwɑːliə, ˈkw-/; sg.: quale /-li/) are defined as instances of subjective, conscious experience. The term qualia derives from the Latin neuter plural form (qualia) of the Latin adjective quālis (Latin pronunciation: [ˈkʷaːlɪs]) meaning "of what sort" or "of what kind" in relation to a specific instance, such as "what it is like to taste a specific apple — this particular apple now".

Examples of qualia include the perceived sensation of pain of a headache, the taste of wine, and the redness of an evening sky. As qualitative characteristics of sensation, qualia stand in contrast to propositional attitudes,[1] where the focus is on beliefs about experience rather than what it is directly like to be experiencing.

American philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce introduced the term quale in philosophy in 1866, and in 1929 C. I. Lewis was the first to use the term "qualia" in its generally agreed upon modern sense. Frank Jackson later defined qualia as "...certain features of the bodily sensations especially, but also of certain perceptual experiences, which no amount of purely physical information includes". Philosopher and cognitive scientist Daniel Dennett suggested that qualia was "an unfamiliar term for something that could not be more familiar to each of us: the ways things seem to us".

The nature and existence of qualia under various definitions remain controversial. Much of the debate over the importance of qualia hinges on the definition of the term, and various philosophers emphasize or deny the existence of certain features of qualia. Some philosophers of mind, like Daniel Dennett, argue that qualia do not exist. Other philosophers, as well as neuroscientists and neurologists, believe qualia exist and that the desire by some philosophers to disregard qualia is based on an erroneous interpretation of what constitutes science.[2]

Definitions[edit]

Many definitions of qualia have been proposed. One of the simpler, broader definitions is: "The 'what it is like' character of mental states. The way it feels to have mental states such as pain, seeing red, smelling a rose, etc."[3]

C.S. Peirce introduced the term quale in philosophy in 1866,[4][5] and in 1929 C.I. Lewis was the first to use the term "qualia" in its generally agreed upon modern sense.[5]

There are recognizable qualitative characters of the given, which may be repeated in different experiences, and are thus a sort of universals; I call these "qualia." But although such qualia are universals, in the sense of being recognized from one to another experience, they must be distinguished from the properties of objects. Confusion of these two is characteristic of many historical conceptions, as well as of current essence-theories. The quale is directly intuited, given, and is not the subject of any possible error because it is purely subjective.[5]: 121 

Frank Jackson later defined qualia as "...certain features of the bodily sensations especially, but also of certain perceptual experiences, which no amount of purely physical information includes".[6]: 273 

Daniel Dennett suggested that qualia was "an unfamiliar term for something that could not be more familiar to each of us: the ways things seem to us".[7] He identifies four properties that are commonly ascribed to qualia.[7] According to these, qualia are:

  1. ineffable – they cannot be communicated, or apprehended by any means other than direct experience.
  2. intrinsic – they are non-relational properties, which do not change depending on the experience's relation to other things.
  3. private – all interpersonal comparisons of qualia are systematically impossible.
  4. directly or immediately apprehensible by consciousness – to experience a quale is to know one experiences a quale, and to know all there is to know about that quale.

If qualia of this sort exist, then a normally sighted person who sees red would be unable to describe the experience of this perception in such a way that a listener who has never experienced color will be able to know everything there is to know about that experience. Though it is possible to make an analogy, such as "red looks hot", or to provide a description of the conditions under which the experience occurs, such as "it's the color you see when light of 700-nm wavelength is directed at you", supporters of this definition of qualia contend that such descriptions cannot provide a complete description of the experience.[8]: 154 

Another way of defining qualia is as "raw feels". A raw feel is a perception in and of itself, considered entirely in isolation from any effect it might have on behavior and behavioral disposition.[9] In contrast, a cooked feel is that perception seen in terms of its effects. For example, the perception of the taste of wine is an ineffable, raw feel, while the behavioral reaction one has to the warmth or bitterness caused by that taste of wine would be a cooked feel. Cooked feels are not qualia.[10]

Arguably, the idea of hedonistic utilitarianism, where the ethical value of things is determined from the amount of subjective pleasure or pain they cause, is dependent on the existence of qualia.[11][12][improper synthesis?]

Arguments regarding the existence of qualia[edit]

Since, by definition, qualia cannot be fully conveyed verbally, they also cannot be demonstrated directly in an argument – a more nuanced approach is needed. Arguments for qualia generally come in the form of thought experiments designed to lead one to the conclusion that qualia exist.[13]

Modern philosophy[edit]

Inverted spectrum argument[edit]

Inverted qualia

The inverted spectrum thought experiment, originally developed by John Locke,[14] invites the reader to imagine that they wake up one morning and find that for some unknown reason all the colors in the world have been inverted, i.e. swapped to the hue on the opposite side of a color wheel. Furthermore, they discover that no physical changes have occurred in their brains or bodies that would explain this phenomenon. Supporters of the existence of qualia argue that since we can imagine this happening without contradiction, it follows that we are imagining a change in a property that determines the way things look to us, but that has no physical basis.[15][16] In more detail:

  1. Metaphysical identity requires necessity.[note 1]
  2. By definition, if something is possibly false, it is not necessary.
  3. It is conceivable that different qualia could be produced by the same physical brain-state.[note 2]
  4. If it is conceivable, then it is possible.[note 3]
  5. Since it is possible that different qualia could be produced by the same physical brain-state, they cannot be identical to physical brain states (per 1).
  6. Therefore, qualia are non-physical.[citation needed]

The argument thus claims that if we find the inverted spectrum plausible, we must admit that qualia exist (and are non-physical). Some philosophers find it absurd that armchair theorizing can prove something to exist, and the detailed argument does involve a lot of assumptions about conceivability and possibility, which are open to criticism. Perhaps it is not possible for a given brain state to produce anything other than a given quale in our universe, and that is all that matters.[citation needed]

The idea that an inverted spectrum would be undetectable in practice is also open to criticism on more scientific grounds, by C. L. Hardin, among others.[15][16] As Alex Byrne puts it:

...there are more perceptually distinguishable shades between red and blue than there are between green and yellow, which would make red-green inversion behaviorally detectable. And there are yet further asymmetries. Dark yellow is brown (qualitatively different from yellow), whereas dark blue is blue[...] Similarly, desaturated bluish-red is pink (qualitatively different from saturated bluish-red), whereas desaturated greenish-yellow is similar to saturated greenish-yellow. Again, red is a "warm" color, whereas blue is "cool"—and perhaps this is not a matter of learned associations with temperature.[15]

There is an actual experiment – albeit somewhat obscure – that parallels the inverted spectrum argument. George M. Stratton, professor of psychology at the University of California, Berkeley, performed an experiment in which he wore special prism glasses that caused the external world to appear upside down. After a few days of continually wearing the glasses, he adapted and the external world appeared upright to him. When he removed the glasses, his perception of the external world again returned to the "normal" perceptual state.[19] If this argument provides evidence that qualia exist, it does not necessarily follow that they must be non-physical, because that distinction should be considered a separate epistemological issue.[failed verification]

Analytic philosophy[edit]

"What's it like to be?" argument[edit]

Thomas Nagel argues that while a human might be able to imagine what it is like to be a bat by taking "the bat's point of view", it would still be impossible "to know what it is like for a bat to be a bat." (Townsend's big-eared bat pictured).

American philosopher Thomas Nagel's paper What Is it Like to Be a Bat?[20] is often cited in debates about qualia, though it does not use the word "qualia." Nagel argues that consciousness has an essentially subjective character, a what-it-is-like aspect. He states that "an organism has conscious mental states if and only if there is something that it is like to be that organism – something it is like for the organism."[20] Nagel suggests that this subjective aspect may never be sufficiently accounted for by the objective methods of reductionistic science. He claims that "if we acknowledge that a physical theory of mind must account for the subjective character of experience, we must admit that no presently available conception gives us a clue about how this could be done."[21]: 450  Furthermore, "it seems unlikely that any physical theory of mind can be contemplated until more thought has been given to the general problem of subjective and objective."[21]: 450 

Zombie argument[edit]

Saul Kripke argues that one key consequence of the claim that such things as raw feels, or qualia, can be meaningfully discussed is that it leads to the logical possibility of two entities exhibiting identical behavior in all ways despite one of them entirely lacking qualia.[22] While few claim that such an entity, called a philosophical zombie, actually exists, the possibility is raised as a refutation of physicalism,[23] and in defense of the hard problem of consciousness (the problem of accounting for, in physical terms, subjective, intrinsic, first-person experiences).[24]

The argument holds that it is conceivable for a person to have a duplicate, identical in every physical way, but lacking consciousness, called a "philosophical zombie." It would appear exactly the same as the original person, in both behavior and speech, just without subjective phenomenology. For these zombies to exist, qualia must not arise from any specific part or parts of the brain, for if it did there would be no difference between "normal humans" and philosophical zombies: The zombie/normal-human distinction can only be valid if subjective consciousness is separate from the physical brain.[24]

According to Chalmers, the simplest form of the argument goes as follows:

  1. It is conceivable that there be zombies
  2. If it is conceivable that there be zombies, it is metaphysically possible that there be zombies.
  3. If it is metaphysically possible that there be zombies, then consciousness is non-physical.
  4. Consciousness is nonphysical.[18]: 106 

Former AI researcher Marvin Minsky sees the argument as circular. He says the proposition of something physically identical to a human but without subjective experience assumes that the physical characteristics of humans cannot produce consciousness, which is exactly what the argument claims to prove. In other words, it tries to prove consciousness is nonphysical by assuming consciousness is nonphysical.[25]: 2 

Explanatory gap argument[edit]

Joseph Levine's paper Conceivability, Identity, and the Explanatory Gap takes up where the criticisms of conceivability arguments (such as the inverted spectrum argument and the zombie argument) leave off. Levine agrees that conceivability is a flawed means of establishing metaphysical realities, but points out that even if we come to the metaphysical conclusion that qualia are physical, there is still an explanatory problem.

While I think this materialist response is right in the end, it does not suffice to put the mind-body problem to rest. Even if conceivability considerations do not establish that the mind is in fact distinct from the body, or that mental properties are metaphysically irreducible to physical properties, still they do demonstrate that we lack an explanation of the mental in terms of the physical.[17]

However, such an epistemological or explanatory problem might indicate an underlying metaphysical issue, as even if not proven by conceivability arguments, the non-physicality of qualia is far from ruled out.

In the end, we are right back where we started. The explanatory gap argument doesn't demonstrate a gap in nature, but a gap in our understanding of nature. Of course a plausible explanation for there being a gap in our understanding of nature is that there is a genuine gap in nature. But so long as we have countervailing reasons for doubting the latter, we have to look elsewhere for an explanation of the former.[17]

Knowledge argument[edit]

Did Mary learn something new?

F. C. Jackson offers what he calls the "knowledge argument" for qualia. It goes as follows:

Mary is a brilliant scientist who is, for whatever reason, forced to investigate the world from a black-and-white room via a black-and-white television monitor. She specializes in the neurophysiology of vision and acquires all the physical information there is to obtain about what goes on when we see ripe tomatoes or the sky and use terms like "red", "blue", and so on. She discovers, for example, just which wavelength combinations from the sky stimulate the retina, and exactly how this produces via the central nervous system the contraction of the vocal cords and expulsion of air from the lungs that results in the uttering of the sentence "The sky is blue." What happens when Mary is released from her black-and-white room or is given a color television monitor? Does she learn anything new or not?

Jackson claims that she does.[6]: 130 

This thought experiment has two purposes. First, it is intended to show that qualia exist. If we accept the thought experiment, we believe that upon leaving the room Mary gains something: the knowledge of a particular thing that she did not possess before. That knowledge, Jackson argues, is knowledge of the quale that corresponds to the experience of seeing red, and it must thus be conceded that qualia are real properties, since there is a difference between a person who has access to a particular quale and one who does not.[6]: 130 

The second purpose of this argument is to refute the physicalist account of the mind. Specifically, the knowledge argument is an attack on the physicalist claim about the completeness of physical truths. The challenge posed to physicalism by the knowledge argument runs as follows:

  1. While in the room, Mary has acquired all the physical facts there are about color sensations, including the sensation of seeing red.
  2. When Mary exits the Room and sees a ripe red tomato, she learns a new fact about the sensation of seeing red, namely its subjective character.
  3. Therefore, there are non-physical facts about color sensations. [From 1, 2]
  4. If there are non-physical facts about color sensations, then color sensations are non-physical events.
  5. Therefore, color sensations are non-physical events. [From 3, 4]
  6. If color sensations are non-physical events, then physicalism is false.
  7. Therefore, physicalism is false. [From 5, 6][26]

Early in his career Jackson argued that qualia are epiphenomenal, thus not causally efficacious with respect to the physical world. Jackson does not give a positive justification for this claim – rather, he seems to assert it simply because it defends qualia against the classic problems of dualism. The natural assumption would be that qualia must be causally efficacious in the physical world, though opponents of qualia ask how one could argue for their existence if they did not affect our brains. If qualia are non-physical properties (which they must be in order to constitute an argument against physicalism), proponents of the theory question how they could have a causal effect on the physical world.[clarify] By redefining qualia as epiphenomenal, Jackson attempts to protect them from the demand of playing a causal role.

Later, however, Jackson rejected epiphenomenalism. This, he argues, is because when Mary first sees red, she says "wow", so it must be Mary's qualia that cause her to say "wow", which contradicts epiphenomenalism. Since the Mary's room thought experiment seems to contradict itself, there must be some mistake in the premises of the experiment. This contradiction is often referred to as the "there must be a reply" reply.[27][better source needed]

Proponents of qualia[edit]

Analytic philosophy[edit]

David Chalmers[edit]

David Chalmers

David Chalmers formulated the hard problem of consciousness, which raised the issue of qualia to a new level of importance and acceptance in the field of the philosophy of mind.[28] In 1995 Chalmers argued for what he called "the principle of organizational invariance": if a system such as one of appropriately configured computer hardware reproduces the functional organization of the brain, it will also reproduce the qualia associated with the brain.[29]

E. J. Lowe[edit]

E. J. Lowe denies that indirect realism, wherein which we have access only to sensory features internal to the brain, necessarily implies a Cartesian dualism. He agrees with Bertrand Russell that the way images are received by our retinas, our "retinal images", are connected to "patterns of neural activity in the cortex".[30] He defends a version of the causal theory of perception in which a causal path can be traced between the external object and the perception of it. He is careful to deny that we do any inferring from the sensory field; he believes this allows us to build an access to knowledge on that causal connection. In a later work he moves closer to the non-epistemic argument in that he postulates "a wholly non-conceptual component of perceptual experience".[30]

J. B. Maund[edit]

John Barry Maund, an Australian philosopher of perception, argues that qualia can be described on two levels, a fact that he refers to as "dual coding".[31]

Maund extended his argument with reference to color.[32] Color he sees as a dispositional property, not an objective one. Colors are "virtual properties", which means they are as if things possessed them. Although the naïve view attributes them to objects, they are intrinsic, non-relational, inner experiences. This allows for the different perceptions between person and person, and also leaves aside the claim that external objects are colored.

Moreland Perkins[edit]

In his book Sensing the World,[33] Moreland Perkins argues that qualia need not be identified as their objective sources: a smell, for instance, bears no direct resemblance to the molecular shape that gives rise to it, nor is a toothache actually in the tooth. Like Hobbes he views the process of sensing as complete in itself; as he puts it, it is not like "kicking a football" where an external object is required – it is more like "kicking a kick". This explanation evades the Homunculus Objection, as adhered to by Gilbert Ryle, among others. Ryle was unable to entertain this possibility, protesting that "in effect it explained the having of sensations as the not having of sensations."[34] However, A.J. Ayer called this objection "very weak" as it betrayed an inability to detach the notion of eyes, or indeed any sensory organ, from the neural sensory experience.[35]

Howard Robinson and William Robinson[edit]

Howard Robinson specialized in philosophy of mind. He argued against explanations of sensory experience that reduce them to physical origins. He never regarded the theory of sense data as refuted, instead setting out to refute persuasive objections to it. In the version of the theory he defends what is before conscious perception is taken to be qualia, or mental presentations that are causally linked to external entities, but are not physical in themselves. He is therefore a dualist: one who takes both matter and mind to have real and metaphysically distinct natures. One of his articles[which?] argues against the physicalist for ignoring the fact that sensory experience can be entirely free of representational character. He cites as an example phosphenes (flashes of light from sudden pressure in the brain, e.g. by coughing, or from direct pressure to the retina), and points out that it is counter-intuitive to argue that these are not visual experiences on a par with open-eye seeing.[citation needed]

William Robinson (no relation) takes a similar view in his book, Understanding Phenomenal Consciousness.[36] He is unusual as a dualist in calling for research programs that investigate the relation of qualia to the brain. The problem is so stubborn, he says, that too many philosophers would prefer "to explain it away", but he would rather have it explained and does not see why the effort should not be made.[citation needed] However, he does not expect a straightforward scientific reduction of phenomenal experience to neural architecture; he regards this as a forlorn hope. The qualitative event realism that Robinson espouses sees phenomenal consciousness as non-material events that are caused by brain events but not identical to them.[citation needed]

He refuses to set aside the vividness – and commonness – of mental images, both visual and aural. In this he opposes Daniel Dennett, who has difficulty crediting such experience in others. He is similar to Moreland Perkins in keeping his investigation wide enough to apply to all the senses.[citation needed]

Science[edit]

Physics[edit]

Neuroscience[edit]

Gerald Edelman[edit]

In his book Bright Air, Brilliant Fire, Neuroscientist and Nobel laureate in Physiology / Medicine Gerald Edelman says "that [it] definitely does not seem feasible [...] to ignore completely the reality of qualia". As he sees it, it is impossible to explain color, sensations, and similar experiences "to a 'qualia-free' observer" by description alone. Edelman argues that proposing such a theory of consciousness is proposing "a theory based on a kind of God's-eye view of consciousness" and that any scientific theory requires the assumption "that observers have sensation as well as perception." He concludes by stating that assuming a theory that requires neither could exist "is to indulge the errors of theories that attempt syntactical formulations mapped onto objectivist interpretations – theories that ignore embodiment as a source of meaning. There is no qualia-free scientific observer."[37]: 115 

Antonio Damasio[edit]

Neurologist Antonio Damasio, in his book The Feeling Of What Happens, defines qualia as "the simple sensory qualities to be found in the blueness of the sky or the tone of sound produced by a cello, and the fundamental components of the images in the movie metaphor are thus made of qualia."[38]: 309 

Damasio points out that "in all likelihood, I will never know your thoughts unless you tell me, and you will never know mine until I tell you." The reason he gives for this is that "the mind and its consciousness are first and foremost private phenomena" that are personal, private experiences that should be investigated as such. While he believes that trying to study these experiences "by the study of their behavioral correlates is wrong," he does think they can be studied as "the idea that subjective experiences are not scientifically accessible is nonsense." In his view the way to do this is for "enough observers [to] undertake rigorous observations according to the same experimental design; and [...] that those observations be checked for consistency across observers and that they yield some form of measurement." He also thinks that "subjective observations [...] can inspire objective experiments" and "be explained in terms of the available scientific knowledge".[38]: 307–309 

In his mind:

The resistance found in some scientific quarters to the use of subjective observations is a revisitation of an old argument between behaviorists, who believed that only behaviors, not mental experiences, could be studied objectively, and cognitivists, who believed that studying only behavior did not do justice to human complexity.[38]: 308 

Rodolfo Llinás[edit]

Neurologist Rodolfo Llinás states in his book I of the Vortex that from a strictly neurological perspective, qualia exist and are important to the organism's survival. He argues that qualia were important for the evolution of the nervous system of organisms, including simple organisms such as insects:

There are today two similar beliefs concerning the nature of qualia. The first is that qualia represent an epiphenomenon that is not necessary for the acquisition of consciousness. Second and somewhat related is the belief that while being the basis for consciousness, qualia appeared only in the highest life forms, suggesting that qualia represent a recently evolved central function that is present in only the more advanced brains. This view relegates the more lowly animals, for example ants, to a realm characterized by the absence of subjective experiences of any kind. It implies that these animals are wired with sets of automatic, reflexively organized circuits that provide for survival by maintaining a successful, albeit purely reactive interaction with the ongoing external world. Although primitive creatures such as ants and cockroaches may be wildly successful, for all practical purposes they are biological automatons.

[...] To me, these views lack a proper evolutionary perspective, which is perhaps why qualia are given so little overall emphasis in the study of brain function. We clearly understand that the functional architecture of the brain is a product of the slow tumblings of evolution and that brain function implements what natural selection has found to be the most beneficial in terms of species survivability. What is not often understood is how deeply related qualia truly are to the evolutionary, functional structure of the brain. [...]

One cannot operate without qualia; they are properties of mind of monumental importance.[39]: 201–221 

Llinás argues that qualia are ancient and necessary for an organism's survival and a product of neuronal oscillation. He gives the evidence of anesthesia of the brain and subsequent stimulation of limbs to demonstrate that qualia can be "turned off" by changing only the variable of neuronal oscillation (local brain electrical activity), while all other connections remain intact. He argues for an oscillatory-electrical origin of qualia, or important aspects thereof.[39]: 202–207 

Vilayanur Ramachandran[edit]
Vilayanur S. Ramachandran

Vilayanur S. Ramachandran and William Hirstein[40] proposed three laws of qualia (with a fourth later added), which are "functional criteria that need to be fulfilled in order for certain neural events to be associated with qualia" by philosophers of the mind:

  1. Qualia are irrevocable and indubitable. You don't say 'maybe it is red but I can visualize it as green if I want to'. An explicit neural representation of red is created that invariably and automatically 'reports' this to higher brain centres.
  2. Once the representation is created, what can be done with it is open-ended. You have the luxury of choice, e.g., if you have the percept of an apple you can use it to tempt Adam, to keep the doctor away, bake a pie, or just to eat. Even though the representation at the input level is immutable and automatic, the output is potentially infinite. This isn't true for, say, a spinal reflex arc where the output is also inevitable and automatic. Indeed, a paraplegic can even have an erection and ejaculate without an orgasm.
  3. Short-term memory. The input invariably creates a representation that persists in short-term memory – long enough to allow time for choice of output. Without this component, again, you get just a reflex arc.
  4. Attention. Qualia and attention are closely linked. You need attention to fulfill criterion number two; to choose. A study of circuits involved in attention, therefore, will shed much light on the riddle of qualia.[41]

These authors approach qualia from an empirical perspective and not as a logical or philosophical problem. They wonder how qualia evolved, and in doing so consider a skeptical point of view in which, since the objective scientific description of the world is complete without qualia, it is nonsense to ask why they evolved or what they are for. However they decide against this skeptical view.

Based on the parsimony principle of Occam's razor, one could accept epiphenomenalism and deny qualia since they are not necessary for a description of the functioning of the brain. However, they argue that Occam's razor is not useful for scientific discovery.[40] For example, the discovery of relativity in physics was not the product of accepting Occam's razor but rather of rejecting it and asking the question of whether a deeper generalization, not required by the currently available data, was true and would allow for unexpected predictions. Most scientific discoveries arise, these authors argue, from ontologically promiscuous conjectures[clarification needed] that do not come from current data.

The authors then point out that skepticism might be justified in the philosophical field, but that science is the wrong place for skepticism, such as asking if "your red is not my green" or if we can be logically certain that we are not dreaming. Science, these authors assert, deals with what is probably true, beyond reasonable doubt, not with what can be known with complete and absolute certainty. The authors say that most neuroscientists and even most psychologists dispute the very existence of the "problem" of qualia.[40]

Critics of qualia[edit]

Daniel Dennett[edit]

Daniel Dennett

In Consciousness Explained[42] and Quining Qualia,[43] Daniel Dennett argues against qualia by claiming that the "knowledge argument" breaks down if one tries to apply it practically. In a series of thought experiments, which he calls intuition pumps, he brings qualia into the world of neurosurgery, clinical psychology, and psychological experimentation. He argues that, once the concept of qualia is so imported, we can either make no use of it, or the questions introduced by it are unanswerable precisely because of the special properties defining qualia.[42]: 398–406 

In Dennett's updated version of the inverted spectrum thought experiment, which he calls alternative neurosurgery, you again awake to find that your qualia have been inverted – grass appears red, the sky appears orange, etc. According to the original account, you should be immediately aware that something has gone horribly wrong. Dennett argues, however, that it is impossible to know whether the diabolical neurosurgeons have indeed inverted your qualia (e.g. by tampering with your optic nerve), or have simply inverted your connection to memories of past qualia. Since both operations would produce the same result, you would have no means on your own to tell which operation has actually been conducted, and you are thus in the odd position of not knowing whether there has been a change in your "immediately apprehensible" qualia.[43]

Dennett argues that for qualia to be taken seriously as a component of experience – for them to make sense as a discrete concept – it must be possible to show that:

  1. it is possible to know that a change in qualia has occurred, as opposed to a change in something else;
         or that
  2. there is a difference between having a change in qualia and not having one.

Dennett attempts to show that we cannot satisfy (a) either through introspection or through observation, and that qualia's very definition undermines its chances of satisfying (b).[43]

Supporters of qualia point out that in order for you to notice a change in qualia, you must compare your current qualia with your memories of past qualia. Arguably, such a comparison would involve immediate assessment of your current qualia and your memories of past qualia, but not of the past qualia themselves. Furthermore, modern functional brain imaging has increasingly suggested that the memory of an experience is processed in similar ways, and in similar zones of the brain, as the original perception.[44]

This may mean that there would be asymmetric outcomes between altering the mechanism of perception of qualia and altering the memory of that qualia. If the diabolical neurosurgery altered the immediate perception of qualia, the inversion might not be noticed directly, since the brain zones which re-process the memories would invert the remembered qualia. On the other hand, alteration of the qualia memories themselves would be processed without inversion, and thus you would perceive them as an inversion. Thus, you might know immediately if memory of your qualia had been altered, but might not know if immediate qualia were inverted or whether the diabolical neurosurgeons had done a sham procedure.[43]

Dennett responds to the Mary the color scientist thought experiment by arguing that Mary would not, in fact, learn something new if she stepped out of her black and white room to see the color red. Dennett asserts that if she already truly knew "everything about color", that knowledge would include a deep understanding of why and how human neurology causes us to sense the quale of color. Mary would therefore already know exactly what to expect upon seeing red, before ever leaving the room.[45]: 15 

Dennett argues that the misleading aspect of the story is that Mary is supposed to not merely be knowledgeable about color but to actually know all the physical facts about it, which would be a knowledge so deep that it exceeds what can be imagined, and twists our intuitions. If Mary really does know everything physical there is to know about the experience of color, then this effectively grants her almost omniscient powers of knowledge. Using this, she will be able to deduce her own reaction, and figure out exactly what the experience of seeing red will feel like.[45]: 15–16 

Dennett finds that many people find it difficult to see this, so he uses the case of RoboMary to further illustrate what it would be like for Mary to possess such a vast knowledge of the physical workings of the human brain and color vision. RoboMary is an intelligent robot who, instead of having color cameras as eyes, has a software lock such that they are only able to perceive black and white and shades in-between.[45]: 27–28 

RoboMary can examine the computer brain of similar non-color-locked robots when they see red, and see exactly how they react and what kinds of impulses occur. RoboMary can also construct a simulation of her own brain, unlock the simulation's color-lock and, with reference to the other robots, simulate exactly how this simulation of herself reacts to seeing red. RoboMary naturally has control over all of her internal states except for the color-lock. With the knowledge of her simulation's internal states upon seeing red, RoboMary can put her own internal states directly into the states they would be in upon seeing red. In this way, without ever actually seeing red through her cameras, she will know exactly what it is like to see red.[45]: 28 

Dennett uses this example as an attempt to show us that Mary's all-encompassing physical knowledge makes her own internal states as transparent as those of a robot or computer, and it is as straightforward for her to figure out exactly how it feels to see red.[45]: 16–17 

Perhaps Mary's failure to learn exactly what seeing red feels like is simply a failure of language, or a failure of our ability to describe experiences. An alien race with a different method of communication or description might be perfectly able to teach their version of Mary exactly how seeing the color red would feel. Perhaps it is simply a uniquely human failing to communicate first-person experiences from a third-person perspective. Dennett suggests that the description might even be possible using English. He uses a simpler version of the Mary thought experiment to show how this might work. What if Mary was in a room without triangles and was prevented from seeing or making any triangles? An English-language description of just a few words would be sufficient for her to imagine what it is like to see a triangle – she can simply and directly visualize a triangle in her mind. Similarly, Dennett proposes, it is perfectly, logically, possible that the quale of what it is like to see red could eventually be described in an English-language description of millions or billions of words.[43]

In Are we explaining consciousness yet?,[46] Dennett approves of an account of qualia defined as the deep, rich collection of individual neural responses that are too fine-grained for language to capture. For instance, a person might have an alarming reaction to yellow because of a yellow car that hit her previously, and someone else might have a nostalgic reaction to a comfort food. These effects are too individual-specific to be captured by English words. "If one dubs this inevitable residue qualia, then qualia are guaranteed to exist, but they are just more of the same, dispositional properties that have not yet been entered in the catalog".[46]

Paul Churchland[edit]

According to Paul Churchland, Mary might be considered akin to a feral child who suffered extreme isolation during childhood. Technically when Mary leaves the room, she would not have the ability to see or know what the color red is, as a brain has to learn and develop how to see colors. Patterns need to form in the V4 section of the visual cortex, which occurs via exposure to wavelengths of light. This exposure needs to occur during the early stages of brain development. In Mary's case, the identifications and categorizations of color will only be in respect to representations of black and white.[47]

Gary Drescher[edit]

In his book Good and Real,[48] Gary Drescher compares qualia with "gensyms" (generated symbols) in Common Lisp. These are objects that Lisp treats as having no properties or components, which can only be identified as equal or not equal to other objects. Drescher explains, "we have no introspective access to whatever internal properties make the red gensym recognizably distinct from the green [...] even though we know the sensation when we experience it."[48] Under this interpretation of qualia, Drescher responds to the Mary thought experiment by noting that "knowing about red-related cognitive structures and the dispositions they engender – even if that knowledge were implausibly detailed and exhaustive – would not necessarily give someone who lacks prior color-experience the slightest clue whether the card now being shown is of the color called red." However, this does not imply that our experience of red is non-mechanical, as "gensyms are a routine feature of computer-programming languages".[21]: 82 

David Lewis[edit]

David K. Lewis introduced a hypothesis about types of knowledge and their transmission in qualia cases. Lewis agrees that Mary cannot learn what red looks like through her monochrome physicalist studies, but he proposes that this does not matter. Learning transmits information, but experiencing qualia does not transmit information: it communicates abilities. When Mary sees red, she does not acquire any new information; she instead gains new abilities. Now she can remember what red looks like, imagine what other red things might look like and recognize further instances of redness.

Lewis states that Jackson's thought experiment uses the phenomenal information hypothesis – that is, that the new knowledge that Mary gains upon seeing red is phenomenal information. Lewis then proposes a different ability hypothesis that differentiates between two types of knowledge: knowledge "that" (information) and knowledge "how" (abilities). Normally the two are entangled; ordinary learning is also an experience of the subject concerned, and people learn both information (for instance, that Freud was a psychologist) and gain ability (to recognize images of Freud). However, in the thought experiment, Mary can use ordinary learning only to gain "that" knowledge. She is prevented from using experience to gain the "how" knowledge that would allow her to remember, imagine and recognize the color red.

We have the intuition that Mary has been deprived of some vital data to do with the experience of redness. It is also uncontroversial that some things cannot be learned inside the room; for example, Mary cannot learn how to ski within the room. Lewis has articulated that information and ability are potentially different things. In this way, physicalism is still compatible with the conclusion that Mary gains new knowledge. It is also useful for considering other instances of qualia – "being a bat" is an ability, so it is "how" knowledge.[49]

Marvin Minsky[edit]

Marvin Minsky

Artificial intelligence researcher Marvin Minsky thinks the problems posed by qualia are essentially issues of complexity, or rather of mistaking complexity for simplicity.

Now, a philosophical dualist might then complain: "You've described how hurting affects your mind – but you still can't express how hurting feels." This, I maintain, is a huge mistake – that attempt to reify "feeling" as an independent entity, with an essence that's indescribable. As I see it, feelings are not strange alien things. It is precisely those cognitive changes themselves that constitute what "hurting" is – and this also includes all those clumsy attempts to represent and summarize those changes. The big mistake comes from looking for some single, simple, "essence" of hurting, rather than recognizing that this is the word we use for complex rearrangement of our disposition of resources.[50]

Michael Tye[edit]

Michael Tye

Michael Tye believes there are no qualia, no "veils of perception" between us and the referents of our thought. He describes our experience of an object in the world as "transparent", meaning that no matter what private understandings and/or misunderstandings we may have of something, it is still there before us in reality. The idea that qualia intervene between ourselves and their origins he regards as a "massive error. That is just not credible. It seems totally implausible [...] that visual experience is systematically misleading in this way." He continues: "the only objects of which you are aware are the external ones making up the scene before your eyes."[21]: 46-47 

From this he concludes "that there are no such qualities of experiences. They are qualities of external surfaces (and volumes and films), if they are qualities of anything." Thus he believes we can take our experiences at face value since there is no fear of losing contact with the realness of physical objects.[21]: 49 

In Tye's thought there is no question of qualia without information being contained within them; it is always "an awareness that" and always "representational". He characterizes the perception of children as a misperception of referents that are undoubtedly as present for them as they are for grown-ups. As he puts it, they may not know that "the house is dilapidated", but there is no doubt about their seeing the house. After-images are dismissed as presenting no problem for the transparency theory because, as he puts it, after-images being illusory, there is nothing that one sees.[21]: 58–59 

Tye proposes that phenomenal experience has five basic elements, for which he has coined the acronym PANIC – Poised, Abstract, Nonconceptual, Intentional Content.[21]: 63 

  • "Poised" - the phenomenal experience is always present to the understanding, whether or not the agent is able to apply a concept to it.
  • "Abstract" - it is unclear whether you are in touch with a concrete object (for example, someone may feel a pain in an amputated limb).
  • "Nonconceptual" - phenomenon can exist although one does not have the concept by which to recognize it.
  • "Intentional (Content)" - it represents something, whether or not the observer is taking advantage of that fact.

Tye adds that the experience is like a map in that, in most cases, it goes beyond the shapes, edges, volumes, etc. in the world – you may not be reading the a map but, as with an actual map there is a reliable match with what it is mapping. This is why Tye calls his theory representationalism, makes it plain that Tye believes that he has retained a direct contact with what produces the phenomena and is therefore not hampered by any trace of a "veil of perception".[51]

Roger Scruton[edit]

Roger Scruton, while skeptical that neurobiology can tell us much about consciousness, believes qualia is an incoherent concept, and that Wittgenstein's private language argument effectively disproves it. Scruton writes,

The belief that these essentially private features of mental states exist, and that they form the introspectible essence of whatever possesses them, is grounded in a confusion, one that Wittgenstein tried to sweep away in his arguments against the possibility of a private language. When you judge that I am in pain, it is on the basis of my circumstances and behavior, and you could be wrong. When I ascribe a pain to myself, I don't use any such evidence. I don't find out that I am in pain by observation, nor can I be wrong. But that is not because there is some other fact about my pain, accessible only to me, which I consult in order to establish what I am feeling. For if there were this inner private quality, I could misperceive it; I could get it wrong, and I would have to find out whether I am in pain. To describe my inner state, I would also have to invent a language, intelligible only to me – and that, Wittgenstein plausibly argues, is impossible. The conclusion to draw is that I ascribe pain to myself not on the basis of some inner quale but on no basis at all.[52]

In his book On Human Nature,[53] Scruton poses a potential line of criticism to this, which is that while Wittgenstein's private language argument does disprove the concept of reference to qualia, or the idea that we can talk, even to ourselves, of their nature; it does not disprove their existence altogether. Scruton believes that this is a valid criticism, and this is why he stops short of actually saying that qualia do not exist, and instead merely suggests that we should abandon the concept. However, he quotes Wittgenstein in response: "Whereof one cannot speak, thereof one must be silent."[53]

See also[edit]

Explanatory notes[edit]

  1. ^ See metaphysical identity and necessity
  2. ^ The premise of the thought experiment.
  3. ^ For an explanation of conceivability, see Levine, 1999,[17] Chalmers, 2003,[18]: 105–106  or philosophical zombie.

References[edit]

Citations[edit]

  1. ^ Kriegel, Uriah (2014). Kriegel, Uriah (ed.). Current controversies in philosophy of mind. New York, NY: Routledge. p. 201. ISBN 978-0-415-53086-6.
  2. ^
  3. ^ Eliasmith, Chris (2004-05-11). "Qualia". Philosophy. Dictionary of Philosophy of Mind. Canada: University of Waterloo. Retrieved 2010-12-03.
  4. ^
    • Peirce, Charles S. (August 22, 1982) [1866]. Fisch, Max Harold (ed.). Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition, Volume 1: 1857-1866. Vol. 1. Indiana Univ. Press. pp. 477–478. ISBN 978-0-253-37201-7.
    • Tye, Michael (2018). "Qualia". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2021 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  5. ^ a b c Lewis, Clarence Irving (1929). Mind and the world-order: outline of a theory of knowledge. New York: Dover publ. p. 121. ISBN 978-0-486-26564-3.
  6. ^ a b c Jackson, Frank (April 1982). "Epiphenomenal Qualia". The Philosophical Quarterly. 32 (127): 127–136. doi:10.2307/2960077. JSTOR 2960077.
  7. ^ a b Dennett, Daniel (1985-11-21). Quining Qualia. Oxford University Press. Retrieved 2020-05-19.
  8. ^ Schrödinger, Erwin (2001) [1958]. What is life? the physical aspect of the living cell. Cambridge paperbacks Science (Repr ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press. ISBN 978-0-521-42708-1.
  9. ^ Shevlin, Henry (10 September 2019). "Qualia and Raw Feels". Rebus Community. Retrieved 22 July 2023.
  10. ^ Schulman, Ari. "What Is It Like to Know?". The New Atlantis (Essay). Winter 2017 (51): 45–62. Retrieved 2023-07-22.
  11. ^ Levy, Neil; Ariyan, S.; Glenn, W. W.; Seashore, J. H. (2014-01-01). "The Value of Consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Studies: Controversies in Science & the Humanities. 21 (1–2): 127–138. doi:10.1097/00006534-198506000-00022. ISSN 1355-8250. PMC 4001209. PMID 24791144.
  12. ^ Shepherd, Joshua (2018). Consciousness and moral status. Routledge focus on philosophy. London New York: Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group. hdl:20.500.12657/30007. ISBN 978-1-315-39634-7.
  13. ^ Nida-Rümelin, Martine; O Conaill, Donnchadh; Broad, C.D. (1925) (2021). "Qualia: The Knowledge Argument". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Qualia knowledge (Summer 2021 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.{{cite encyclopedia}}: CS1 maint: numeric names: authors list (link)
  14. ^ Locke, John (1975) [1689]. "Essay Concerning Human Understanding". An Essay Concerning Humane Understanding. Vol. 1 (2 ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Volume II, chapter xxxii, section 15.
  15. ^ a b c Byrne, Alex (2020). "Inverted Qualia". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2020 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2010-12-03 – via Plato.stanford.edu.
  16. ^ a b Hardin, Clyde L. (Dec 1987). "Qualia and Materialism: Closing the Explanatory Gap". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 48 (2): 281–298. doi:10.2307/2107629. JSTOR 2107629.
  17. ^ a b c Levine, J. (1999). "Conceivability, Identity, and the Explanatory Gap". In Hameroff, Stuart R.; Kaszniak, Alfred W.; Chalmers, David John (eds.). Toward a science of consciousness. Complex adaptive systems. Cambridge (Mass.): MIT press. pp. 3–12. ISBN 978-0-262-58181-3. Archived from the original on 2010-08-31. Retrieved 2023-07-19.
  18. ^ a b Chalmers, David J. (2007-12-13). Stich, Stephen P.; Warfield, Ted A. (eds.). The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind. Malden, MA, USA: Blackwell Publishing Ltd. pp. 102–142. doi:10.1002/9780470998762.ch5.
  19. ^ Stratton, George M. (1896). "Some preliminary experiments on vision" (PDF). Psychological Review.
  20. ^ a b Nagel, Thomas (Oct 1974). "What Is It Like to Be a Bat?". The Philosophical Review. 83 (4): 435–450. doi:10.2307/2183914. JSTOR 2183914.
  21. ^ a b c d e f g Tye, Michael (2000). Consciousness, Color, and Content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  22. ^ Kripke, Saul A.; Hörzer, Gregor M. (2021). Identity and necessity: englisch/deutsch = Identität und Notwendigkeit. Reclams Universal-Bibliothek. Ditzingen: Reclam. ISBN 978-3-15-014005-5.
  23. ^ Kripke, Saul A. (1977), "Naming and Necessity", in Davidson, Donald; Harman, Gilbert (eds.), Semantics of Natural Language, Synthese library (2. ed., 3. print ed.), Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 253–355, doi:10.1007/978-94-010-2557-7_9, ISBN 978-90-277-0310-1, retrieved 2023-07-18
  24. ^ a b Kirk, Robert. "Zombie". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2009s ed.). Retrieved 2023-07-19.
  25. ^ Marvin, Minsky (1998-02-26). "Consciousness is a Big Suitcase". Edge.org (Interview). Interviewed by John Brockman. Edge Foundation, Inc. Retrieved 2023-07-19.
  26. ^ Kind, Amy (2020-03-17). Philosophy of Mind: The Basics. Routledge. pp. 66–67. doi:10.4324/9781315750903. ISBN 9781315750903. S2CID 214260059. Retrieved 2023-07-22.
  27. ^ Stone, Jim (2010-04-14). "The Knowledge Argument". PhilPapers. Retrieved 2023-07-19.
  28. ^ Kind, Amy. "Qualia". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 6 November 2022.
  29. ^ Chalmers, D. (1995). "Absent qualia, fading qualia, dancing qualia". In Metzinger, Thomas (ed.). Conscious Experience. Imprint Academic.
  30. ^ a b Lowe, Edward Jonathan (1996). Subjects of experience. Cambridge studies in philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge university press. p. 101. ISBN 978-0-521-47503-7.
  31. ^ Maund, J. B. (September 1975). "The Representative Theory Of Perception". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 5 (1): 41–55. doi:10.1080/00455091.1975.10716096. ISSN 0045-5091. S2CID 146937154.
  32. ^
  33. ^ Perkins, Moreland (1983). Sensing the world. Indianapolis, Ind: Hackett. ISBN 978-0-915145-75-1.
  34. ^ Ryle, Gilbert (1949). The concept of mind (Repr. ed.). Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Pr. p. 215. ISBN 978-0-226-73296-1.
  35. ^ Ayer, Alfred J.; Ayer, Alfred Jules (1957). The problem of knowledge. Penguin books Philosophy (Reprinted ed.). Harmondsworth: Penguin Books. p. 107. ISBN 978-0-14-013547-3.
  36. ^ Robinson, William S.; Robinson, William Spencer (2004). Understanding phenomenal consciousness. Cambridge studies in philosophy (1. publ ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-83463-6.
  37. ^ Edelman, Gerald Maurice (1993). Bright air, brilliant fire: on the matter of the mind. New York: BasicBooks. p. 115. ISBN 978-0-465-00764-6.
  38. ^ a b c Damasio, Antonio R. (2000). The feeling of what happens: body and emotion in the making of consciousness. A Harvest book (1 ed.). San Diego, CA: Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-15-601075-7.
  39. ^ a b Llinás, Rodolfo Riascos; Llinás, Rodolfo R. (2002). I of the vortex: from neurons to self. A Bradford book (1 ed.). Cambridge, Mass. London: MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-62163-2.
  40. ^ a b c Ramachandran, V.S.; Hirstein, W. (1997-05-01). "Three laws of qualia: what neurology tells us about the biological functions of consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 4 (5–6): 429–457.
  41. ^ Ramachandran, V.S.; Hirstein, W. (1 December 2001). "Synaesthesia – a window into perception, thought, and language". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 8 (12): 3–34.
  42. ^ a b Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Back bay books (1 ed.). Boston: Little, Brown. ISBN 978-0-316-18066-5.
  43. ^ a b c d e Dennett, Daniel C. (1988). "Quining qualia". In Marcel, A.; Bisiach, E. (eds.). Consciousness in Modern Science. Oxford University Press. pp. 42–77.
  44. ^ Ungerleider, L. G. (1995-11-03). "Functional brain imaging studies of cortical mechanisms for memory". Science. 270 (5237): 769–775. Bibcode:1995Sci...270..769U. doi:10.1126/science.270.5237.769. ISSN 0036-8075. PMID 7481764. S2CID 37665998.
  45. ^ a b c d e Dennett, Daniel (2006). "What robomary knows". In Alter, Torin Andrew; Walter, Sven (eds.). Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism. Oxford University Press.
  46. ^ a b Dennett, D. (April 2001). "Are we explaining consciousness yet?". Cognition. 79 (1–2): 221–237. doi:10.1016/s0010-0277(00)00130-x. ISSN 0010-0277. PMID 11164029. S2CID 2235514.
  47. ^ Churchland, Paul (2004). "Knowing qualia: A reply to Jackson (with postscript 1997)". In Ludlow, Peter; Nagasawa, Yujin; Stoljar, Daniel (eds.). There's something about Mary: essay on phenomenal consciousness and Frank Jackson's knowledge argument. Cambridge (Mass.): the MIT press. pp. 163–178. ISBN 978-0-262-62189-2.
  48. ^ a b Drescher, Gary L. (2006). Good and real: demystifying paradoxes from physics to ethics. A Bradford book. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. pp. 81–82. ISBN 978-0-262-04233-8 – via Google Books.
  49. ^ Lewis, D.K.; Nagasawa, Yujin; Stoljar, Daniel (2004). "What experience teaches". In Ludlow, Peter; Nagasawa, Yujin; Stoljar, Daniel (eds.). There's something about Mary: essay on phenomenal consciousness and Frank Jackson's knowledge argument. Cambridge (Mass.): the MIT press. pp. 77–103. ISBN 978-0-262-62189-2.
  50. ^ Marvin, Minsky (1998-02-26). "Consciousness is a Big Suitcase". Edge.org (Interview). Interviewed by John Brockman. Edge Foundation, Inc. Retrieved 2023-07-19.
  51. ^
  52. ^ Scruton, Roger (2005-02-01). "The Unobservable Mind". MIT Technology Review. Retrieved 2023-07-19.
  53. ^ a b Scruton, Roger (2017). On human nature. Princeton Oxford: Princeton university press. ISBN 9780691168753.

Other references[edit]

Further reading[edit]

External links[edit]